Empiricism Warning: You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you log in or create an account, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.Anti-spam check. Do not fill this in! {{Short description|Idea that knowledge comes only/mainly from sensory experience}} {{About|the field of philosophy|the album by Borknagar|Empiricism (album){{!}}''Empiricism'' (album)}} {{Use British English|date=August 2019}} {{multiple image|caption_align=center | total_width = 275 <!--image 1--> | image1 = Somer Francis Bacon.jpg | width1 = 700 | height1 = 828 | alt1 = | link1 = | caption1 = [[Francis Bacon]] <!--image 2--> | image2 = Locke-John-LOC.jpg | width2 = 700 | height2 = 828 | alt2 = | link2 = | caption2 = [[John Locke]] <!--image 3--> | image3 = Painting of David Hume.jpg | width3 = 700 | height3 = 828 | alt3 = | link3 = | caption3 = [[David Hume]] }} {{Epistemology sidebar}} {{Research}} In [[philosophy]], '''empiricism''' is an [[Epistemology|epistemological view]] which holds that true knowledge or justification comes only or primarily from [[Empirical evidence|sensory experience]] and [[empirical evidence]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Psillos|first1=Stathis|last2=Curd|first2=Martin|title=The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science|date=2010|publisher=Routledge|location=London|isbn=978-0415546133|pages=129–38|edition=1. publ. in paperback}}</ref> It is one of several competing views within epistemology, along with [[rationalism]] and [[philosophical skepticism|skepticism]]. Empiricists argue that empiricism is a more reliable method of finding the truth than purely using [[logical reasoning]], because humans have cognitive [[Bias|biases]] and limitations which lead to errors of judgement.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Francis Bacon and the Four Idols of the Mind |url=https://fs.blog/francis-bacon-four-idols-mind/}}</ref> Empiricism emphasizes the central role of [[empirical evidence]] in the formation of ideas, rather than [[innate idea]]s or [[traditions]].<ref>{{Cite book| last = Baird | first = Forrest E. |author2=Walter Kaufmann | title = From Plato to Derrida | publisher = Pearson Prentice Hall | year = 2008 | location = Upper Saddle River, New Jersey | isbn = 978-0-13-158591-1 }}{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> Empiricists may argue that traditions (or customs) arise due to relations of previous sensory experiences.<ref name="Hume1" /> Historically, empiricism was associated with the "[[blank slate]]" concept (''tabula rasa''), according to which the human mind is "blank" at birth and develops its thoughts only through later experience.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Scheibe, Erhard.|title=Between rationalism and empiricism : selected papers in the philosophy of physics|date=2001|publisher=Springer|isbn=0-387-98520-4|oclc=45888831}}</ref> Empiricism in the [[philosophy of science]] emphasizes evidence, especially as discovered in [[experiment]]s. It is a fundamental part of the [[scientific method]] that all hypotheses and theories must be tested against observations of the natural world rather than resting solely on ''[[A priori (philosophy)|a priori]]'' reasoning, [[intuition (knowledge)|intuition]], or [[revelation]]. Empiricism, often used by [[Natural Scientists|natural scientists]], believes that "knowledge is based on experience" and that "knowledge is tentative and probabilistic, subject to continued revision and [[Falsifiability|falsification]]".<ref>Shelley, M. (2006). Empiricism. In F. English (Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational leadership and administration. (pp. 338–39). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc.</ref> Empirical research, including experiments and validated measurement tools, guides the scientific method. ==Etymology== The English term ''empirical'' derives from the [[Ancient Greek]] word ἐμπειρία, ''empeiria'', which is cognate with and translates to the Latin ''experientia'', from which the words ''experience'' and ''experiment'' are derived.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/empiric|title=Definition of EMPIRIC|website=www.merriam-webster.com|date=20 January 2024 }}</ref> ==Background== {{Main|Empirical method}} A central concept in [[science]] and the [[scientific method]] is that conclusions must be ''empirically'' based on the evidence of the senses. Both [[natural science|natural]] and [[social science]]s use working [[hypothesis|hypotheses]] that are [[testable]] by [[observation]] and [[experiment]]. The term ''semi-empirical'' is sometimes used to describe theoretical methods that make use of basic [[axiom]]s, established scientific laws, and previous experimental results to engage in reasoned model building and theoretical inquiry. Philosophical empiricists hold no knowledge to be properly inferred or deduced unless it is derived from one's sense-based experience.<ref>Markie, P. (2004), "Rationalism vs. Empiricism" in Edward D. Zalta (ed.), ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism/ Eprint].</ref> In [[epistemology]] (theory of knowledge) empiricism is typically contrasted with [[rationalism]], which holds that knowledge may be derived from [[reason]] independently of the senses, and in the [[philosophy of mind]] it is often contrasted with [[innatism]], which holds that some knowledge and ideas are already present in the mind at birth. However, many Enlightenment rationalists and empiricists still made concessions to each other. For example, the empiricist [[John Locke]] admitted that some knowledge (e.g. knowledge of God's existence) could be arrived at through [[Intuition (knowledge)|intuition]] and reasoning alone. Similarly, [[Robert Boyle]], a prominent advocate of the experimental method, held that we also have innate ideas.<ref>Loeb, Luis E. (1981), ''From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy'', Ithaca, Cornell University Press.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref><ref>Engfer, Hans-Jürgen (1996), ''Empirismus versus Rationalismus? Kritik eines philosophiegeschichtlichen Schemas'', Paderborn: Schöningh.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> At the same time, the main continental [[rationalist]]s ([[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], and [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]]) were also advocates of the empirical "scientific method".<ref>Buckle, Stephen (1999), "British Sceptical Realism. A Fresh Look at the British Tradition", ''European Journal of Philosophy'', 7, pp. 1–2.</ref><ref>Peter Anstey, "[https://blogs.otago.ac.nz/emxphi/2010/09/esp-is-best/ ESP is best] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131231075256/https://blogs.otago.ac.nz/emxphi/2010/09/esp-is-best/ |date=2013-12-31 }}", ''[https://blogs.otago.ac.nz/emxphi/ Early Modern Experimental Philosophy]'', 2010.</ref> ==History== ===Early empiricism=== {{multiple image|total_width=250 | image1 = kanada.png |caption1= [[Kanada (philosopher)|Maharishi Kanada]] | image2 = Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg | caption2= [[Aristotle]] }} Between 600 and 200 BCE, the [[Vaisheshika]] [[darśana|school of Hindu philosophy]], founded by the ancient Indian philosopher [[Kanada (philosopher)|Kanada]], accepted [[perception]] and [[inference]] as the only two reliable sources of knowledge.<ref name=dpsb>DPS Bhawuk (2011), Spirituality and Indian Psychology (Editor: Anthony Marsella), Springer, {{ISBN|978-1-4419-8109-7}}, page 172</ref><ref name=eliott>Eliott Deutsche (2000), in Philosophy of Religion : Indian Philosophy Vol 4 (Editor: Roy Perrett), Routledge, {{ISBN|978-0815336112}}, pages 245-248</ref><ref name=jag>John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press, {{ISBN|978-0791430675}}, page 238</ref> This is enumerated in his work ''[[Vaiśeṣika Sūtra]]''. The [[Charvaka]] school held similar beliefs, asserting that perception is the only reliable source of knowledge while inference obtains knowledge with uncertainty. The earliest Western proto-empiricists were the [[empiric school]] of ancient Greek medical practitioners, founded in 330 BCE.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.greekmedicine.net/whos_who/Alexander_the_Great.html|title=Greek Medicine: Alexander the Great|website=www.greekmedicine.net}}</ref> Its members rejected the doctrines of the [[dogmatic school]], preferring to rely on the observation of ''[[phantasiai]]'' (i.e., phenomena, the appearances).<ref name=sini>Sini, Carlo (2004), "Empirismo", in Gianni Vattimo et al. (eds.), ''Enciclopedia Garzanti della Filosofia''.</ref> The Empiric school was closely allied with the [[pyrrhonism|Pyrrhonist]] school of philosophy, which made the philosophical case for their proto-empiricism. The notion of ''[[tabula rasa]]'' ("clean slate" or "blank tablet") connotes a view of mind the as an originally blank or empty recorder (Locke used the words "white paper") on which experience leaves marks. This denies that humans have [[innate ideas]]. The notion dates back to [[Aristotle]], {{Circa|350 BC}}: {{Blockquote| What the mind (''[[nous]]'') thinks must be in it in the same sense as letters are on a tablet (''grammateion'') which bears no actual writing (''grammenon''); this is just what happens in the case of the mind. (Aristotle, ''[[On the Soul]]'', 3.4.430<sup>a</sup>1).}} Aristotle's explanation of how this was possible was not strictly empiricist in a modern sense, but rather based on his theory of [[potentiality and actuality]], and experience of sense perceptions still requires the help of the [[active intellect|active ''nous'']]. These notions contrasted with [[Platonism|Platonic]] notions of the human mind as an entity that pre-existed somewhere in the heavens, before being sent down to join a body on Earth (see Plato's ''[[Phaedo]]'' and ''Apology'', as well as others). Aristotle was considered to give a more important position to sense perception than [[Plato]], and commentators in the Middle Ages summarized one of his positions as "''nihil in intellectu nisi prius fuerit in sensu''" (Latin for "nothing in the intellect without first being in the senses"). This idea was later developed in ancient philosophy by the [[stoicism|Stoic]] school, from about 330 BCE. Stoic epistemology generally emphasizes that the mind starts blank, but acquires knowledge as the outside world is impressed upon it.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Bardzell|first1=Jeffrey|title=Speculative Grammar and Stoic Language Theory in Medieval Allegorical Narrative: From Prudentius to Alan of Lille|date=June 11, 2014|publisher=Routledge|pages=18–19}}</ref> The doxographer [[Aetius (philosopher)|Aetius]] summarizes this view as "When a man is born, the Stoics say, he has the commanding part of his soul like a sheet of paper ready for writing upon."<ref>Diels-Kranz 4.11 translated by {{cite book|last1=Long|first1=A. A.|last2=Sedley|first2=D. N.|title=The Hellenistic Philosophers: Vol. 1|date=1987|publisher=Cambridge|location=Cambridge, Ma|pages=238}}</ref> [[File:Avicenna.jpg|thumb|right|A drawing of [[Avicenna|Ibn Sina]] (Avicenna) from 1271]] ===Islamic Golden Age and Pre-Renaissance (5th to 15th centuries CE)=== During the [[Middle Ages]] (from the 5th to the 15th century CE) Aristotle's theory of ''tabula rasa'' was developed by [[Islamic philosophy|Islamic philosophers]] starting with [[Al Farabi]] ({{Circa|872|951 CE}}), developing into an elaborate theory by [[Avicenna]] (c. 980 – 1037 CE)<ref name=Rizvi/> and demonstrated as a [[thought experiment]] by [[Ibn Tufail]].<ref name=Russell/> For Avicenna ([[Avicenna|Ibn Sina]]), for example, the ''tabula rasa'' is a pure potentiality that is actualized through [[education]], and knowledge is attained through "empirical familiarity with objects in this world from which one abstracts universal concepts" developed through a "[[Syllogism|syllogistic]] method of [[reasoning]] in which observations lead to propositional statements which when compounded lead to further abstract concepts". The [[intellect]] itself develops from a [[passive intellect|material intellect]] (''al-'aql al-hayulani''), which is a [[potentiality]] "that can acquire knowledge to the [[active intellect]] (''al-[['aql]] al-fa'il''), the state of the human intellect in conjunction with the perfect source of knowledge".<ref name=Rizvi>Sajjad H. Rizvi (2006), [http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/avicenna.htm Avicenna/Ibn Sina (c. 980–1037)], ''[[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]''</ref> So the immaterial "active intellect", separate from any individual person, is still essential for understanding to occur. In the 12th century CE, the [[Al-Andalus|Andalusian]] [[Muslim]] philosopher and novelist Abu Bakr [[Ibn Tufail]] (known as "Abubacer" or "Ebu Tophail" in the West) included the theory of ''tabula rasa'' as a [[thought experiment]] in his [[Arabic literature|Arabic philosophical novel]], ''[[Hayy ibn Yaqdhan]]'' in which he depicted the development of the mind of a [[feral child]] "from a ''tabula rasa'' to that of an adult, in complete isolation from society" on a [[desert island]], through experience alone. The [[Latin]] translation of his [[philosophical novel]], entitled ''Philosophus Autodidactus'', published by [[Edward Pococke]] the Younger in 1671, had an influence on [[John Locke]]'s formulation of ''tabula rasa'' in ''[[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding]]''.<ref name=Russell>G. A. Russell (1994), ''The 'Arabick' Interest of the Natural Philosophers in Seventeenth-Century England'', pp. 224–62, [[Brill Publishers]], {{ISBN|90-04-09459-8}}</ref> A similar [[Islamic theology|Islamic theological]] novel, ''[[Theologus Autodidactus]]'', was written by the Arab theologian and physician [[Ibn al-Nafis]] in the 13th century. It also dealt with the theme of empiricism through the story of a feral child on a desert island, but departed from its predecessor by depicting the development of the protagonist's mind through contact with society rather than in isolation from society.<ref name="Roubi">Dr. Abu Shadi Al-Roubi (1982), "Ibn Al-Nafis as a philosopher", ''Symposium on Ibn al-Nafis'', Second International Conference on Islamic Medicine: Islamic Medical Organization, Kuwait ([[cf.]] [http://www.islamset.com/isc/nafis/drroubi.html Ibn al-Nafis As a Philosopher] {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080206072116/http://www.islamset.com/isc/nafis/drroubi.html |date=February 6, 2008 }}, ''Encyclopedia of Islamic World'')</ref> During the 13th century [[Thomas Aquinas]] adopted into [[scholasticism]] the [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] position that the senses are essential to the mind. [[Bonaventure]] (1221–1274), one of Aquinas' strongest intellectual opponents, offered some of the strongest arguments in favour of the Platonic idea of the mind. ===Renaissance Italy=== In the late [[renaissance]] various writers began to question the [[medieval]] and [[classical philosophy|classical]] understanding of knowledge acquisition in a more fundamental way. In political and historical writing [[Niccolò Machiavelli]] and his friend [[Francesco Guicciardini]] initiated a new realistic style of writing. Machiavelli in particular was scornful of writers on politics who judged everything in comparison to mental ideals and demanded that people should study the "effectual truth" instead. Their contemporary, [[Leonardo da Vinci]] (1452–1519) said, "If you find from your own experience that something is a fact and it contradicts what some authority has written down, then you must abandon the authority and base your reasoning on your own findings."<ref>"Seeing the Body: The Divergence of Ancient Chineseand Western Medical Illustration", Camillia Matuk, Journal of Biocommunication, Vol. 32, No. 1, 2006, [http://www.sesp.northwestern.edu/docs/publications/6074956944509ac426aaa6.pdf] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170124012747/http://www.sesp.northwestern.edu/docs/publications/6074956944509ac426aaa6.pdf|date=2017-01-24}}</ref> Significantly, an empirical metaphysical system was developed by the Italian philosopher [[Bernardino Telesio]] which had an enormous impact on the development of later Italian thinkers, including Telesio's students [[Antonio Persio]] and [[:it:Sertorio Quattromani|Sertorio Quattromani]], his contemporaries [[Thomas Campanella]] and [[Giordano Bruno]], and later British philosophers such as [[Francis Bacon]], who regarded Telesio as "the first of the moderns".<ref name= Tele> Boenke, Michaela, "Bernardino Telesio", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/telesio/. </ref> Telesio's influence can also be seen on the French philosophers [[René Descartes]] and [[Pierre Gassendi]].<ref name=Tele /> The decidedly anti-Aristotelian and anti-clerical music theorist [[Vincenzo Galilei]] (c. 1520 – 1591), father of [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]] and the inventor of [[monody]], made use of the method in successfully solving musical problems, firstly, of tuning such as the relationship of pitch to string tension and mass in stringed instruments, and to volume of air in wind instruments; and secondly to composition, by his various suggestions to composers in his ''Dialogo della musica antica e moderna'' (Florence, 1581). The Italian word he used for "experiment" was ''esperimento''. It is known that he was the essential pedagogical influence upon the young Galileo, his eldest son (cf. Coelho, ed. ''Music and Science in the Age of Galileo Galilei''), arguably one of the most influential empiricists in history. Vincenzo, through his tuning research, found the underlying truth at the heart of the misunderstood myth of '[[Pythagorean hammers|Pythagoras' hammers]]' (the square of the numbers concerned yielded those musical intervals, not the actual numbers, as believed), and through this and other discoveries that demonstrated the fallibility of traditional authorities, a radically empirical attitude developed, passed on to Galileo, which regarded "experience and demonstration" as the ''sine qua non'' of valid rational enquiry. ===British empiricism<!--'British empiricism' and 'British Empiricism' redirect here-->=== [[File:Thomas Hobbes (portrait).jpg|thumb|Thomas Hobbes]] '''British empiricism'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->, a retrospective characterization, emerged during the 17th century as an approach to [[early modern philosophy]] and [[modern science]]. Although both integral to this overarching transition, [[Francis Bacon]], in England, first [[Novum Organum|advocated for empiricism in 1620]], whereas [[René Descartes]], in France, laid the main groundwork [[Meditations on First Philosophy|upholding rationalism]] around 1640. (Bacon's natural philosophy was influenced by Italian philosopher [[Bernardino Telesio]] and by Swiss physician [[Paracelsus]].)<ref name=Tele /> Contributing later in the 17th century, [[Thomas Hobbes]] and [[Baruch Spinoza]] are retrospectively identified likewise as an empiricist and a rationalist, respectively. In the [[The Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] of the late 17th century, [[John Locke]] in England, and in the 18th century, both [[George Berkeley]] in England and [[David Hume]] in [[Scotland]], all became leading exponents of empiricism, hence the dominance of empiricism in British philosophy. The distinction between rationalism and empiricism was not formally made until [[Immanuel Kant]], in Germany, [[Critique of Pure Reason|around 1780]], who sought to merge the two views.{{citation needed|date=November 2023}} In response to the early-to-mid-17th-century "[[continental rationalism]]", [[John Locke]] (1632–1704) proposed in ''[[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding]]'' (1689) a very influential view wherein the ''only'' knowledge humans can have is ''[[a posteriori]]'', i.e., based upon experience. Locke is famously attributed with holding the proposition that the human mind is a ''[[tabula rasa]]'', a "blank tablet", in Locke's words "white paper", on which the experiences derived from sense impressions as a person's life proceeds are written. There are two sources of our ideas: sensation and reflection. In both cases, a distinction is made between simple and complex ideas. The former are unanalysable, and are broken down into primary and secondary qualities. Primary qualities are essential for the object in question to be what it is. Without specific primary qualities, an object would not be what it is. For example, an apple is an apple because of the arrangement of its atomic structure. If an apple were structured differently, it would cease to be an apple. Secondary qualities are the sensory information we can perceive from its primary qualities. For example, an apple can be perceived in various colours, sizes, and textures but it is still identified as an apple. Therefore, its primary qualities dictate what the object essentially is, while its secondary qualities define its attributes. Complex ideas combine simple ones, and divide into substances, modes, and relations. According to Locke, our knowledge of things is a perception of ideas that are in accordance or discordance with each other, which is very different from the quest for [[certainty]] of [[René Descartes|Descartes]].{{citation needed|date=November 2023}} [[File:George Berkeley by John Smibert.jpg|thumb|upright|right|[[George Berkeley|Bishop George Berkeley]]]] A generation later, the Irish [[Anglican]] bishop [[George Berkeley]] (1685–1753) determined that Locke's view immediately opened a door that would lead to eventual [[atheism]]. In response to Locke, he put forth in his ''[[Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge]]'' (1710) an important challenge to empiricism in which things ''only'' exist either as a ''result'' of their being perceived, or by virtue of the fact that they are an entity doing the perceiving. (For Berkeley, God fills in for humans by doing the perceiving whenever humans are not around to do it.) In his text ''[[Alciphron (book)|Alciphron]]'', Berkeley maintained that any order humans may see in nature is the language or handwriting of God.<ref>Thornton, Stephen (1987) "Berkeley's Theory of Reality" in ''The Journal of the Limerick Philosophical Society'', [http://www.ul.ie/~philos/vol1/berkel.html UL.ie] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110918113600/http://www.ul.ie/~philos/vol1/berkel.html |date=2011-09-18 }}</ref> Berkeley's approach to empiricism would later come to be called [[subjective idealism]].<ref>Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "George Berkeley", vol. 1, p. 297.</ref><ref name="MEP2"/> Scottish philosopher [[David Hume]] (1711–1776) responded to Berkeley's criticisms of Locke, as well as other differences between early modern philosophers, and moved empiricism to a new level of [[skepticism]]. Hume argued in keeping with the empiricist view that all knowledge derives from sense experience, but he accepted that this has implications not normally acceptable to philosophers. He wrote for example, "Locke divides all arguments into demonstrative and probable. On this view, we must say that it is only probable that all men must die or that the sun will rise to-morrow, because neither of these can be demonstrated. But to conform our language more to common use, we ought to divide arguments into demonstrations, proofs, and probabilities—by ‘proofs’ meaning arguments from experience that leave no room for doubt or opposition."<ref name="Hume_human_understanding_chap_prob">{{Cite book|chapter-url=http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4320/4320-h/4320-h.htm|last=Hume|chapter=Of Probability|title=Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals}}</ref> And,<ref name="Hume_human_understanding_chap_nec">{{Cite book|chapter-url=http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4320/4320-h/4320-h.htm|last=Hume|chapter=Of the Idea of a Necessary Connexion|title=Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals}}</ref> {{quote|I believe the most general and most popular explication of this matter, is to say [See Mr. Locke, chapter of power.], that finding from experience, that there are several new productions in matter, such as the motions and variations of body, and concluding that there must somewhere be a power capable of producing them, we arrive at last by this reasoning at the idea of power and efficacy. But to be convinced that this explication is more popular than philosophical, we need but reflect on two very obvious principles. First, That reason alone can never give rise to any original idea, and secondly, that reason, as distinguished from experience, can never make us conclude, that a cause or productive quality is absolutely requisite to every beginning of existence. Both these considerations have been sufficiently explained: and therefore shall not at present be any farther insisted on.|Hume, Section XIV, "Of the idea of necessary connexion", in ''[[A Treatise of Human Nature]]''}} Hume divided all of human knowledge into two categories: ''relations of ideas'' and ''matters of fact'' (see also [[Immanuel Kant|Kant's]] [[analytic-synthetic distinction]]). Mathematical and logical propositions (e.g. "that the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the sum of the squares of the two sides") are examples of the first, while propositions involving some [[Contingency (philosophy)|contingent]] observation of the world (e.g. "the sun rises in the East") are examples of the second. All of people's "ideas", in turn, are derived from their "impressions". For Hume, an "impression" corresponds roughly with what we call a sensation. To remember or to imagine such impressions is to have an "idea". Ideas are therefore the faint copies of sensations.<ref name = Hume1/> [[File:David Hume.jpg|thumb|right|[[David Hume]]'s empiricism led to numerous philosophical schools.]] Hume maintained that no knowledge, even the most basic beliefs about the natural world, can be conclusively established by reason. Rather, he maintained, our beliefs are more a result of accumulated ''habits'', developed in response to accumulated sense experiences. Among his many arguments Hume also added another important slant to the debate about [[scientific method]]—that of the [[problem of induction]]. Hume argued that it requires [[inductive reasoning]] to arrive at the premises for the principle of inductive reasoning, and therefore the justification for inductive reasoning is a circular argument.<ref name = Hume1/> Among Hume's conclusions regarding the problem of induction is that there is no certainty that the future will resemble the past. Thus, as a simple instance posed by Hume, we cannot know with certainty by [[inductive reasoning]] that the sun will continue to rise in the East, but instead come to expect it to do so because it has repeatedly done so in the past.<ref name=Hume1>Hume, D. "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", in Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 2nd edition, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), [[Oxford University Press]], Oxford, UK, 1902 [1748].{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> Hume concluded that such things as belief in an external world and belief in the existence of the self were not rationally justifiable. According to Hume these beliefs were to be accepted nonetheless because of their profound basis in instinct and custom. Hume's lasting legacy, however, was the doubt that his skeptical arguments cast on the legitimacy of inductive reasoning, allowing many skeptics who followed to cast similar doubt.{{citation needed|date=November 2023}} ===Phenomenalism=== {{Main|Phenomenalism}} Most of Hume's followers have disagreed with his conclusion that belief in an external world is ''rationally'' unjustifiable, contending that Hume's own principles implicitly contained the rational justification for such a belief, that is, beyond being content to let the issue rest on human instinct, custom and habit.<ref>Morick, H. (1980), Challenges to Empiricism, Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN.</ref> According to an extreme empiricist theory known as [[phenomenalism]], anticipated by the arguments of both Hume and George Berkeley, a physical object is a kind of construction out of our experiences.<ref>Marconi, Diego (2004), "Fenomenismo"', in [[Gianni Vattimo]] and Gaetano Chiurazzi (eds.), ''L'Enciclopedia Garzanti di Filosofia'', 3rd edition, Garzanti, Milan, Italy.</ref> Phenomenalism is the view that physical objects, properties, events (whatever is physical) are reducible to mental objects, properties, events. Ultimately, only mental objects, properties, events, exist—hence the closely related term [[subjective idealism]]. By the phenomenalistic line of thinking, to have a visual experience of a real physical thing is to have an experience of a certain kind of group of experiences. This type of set of experiences possesses a constancy and coherence that is lacking in the set of experiences of which hallucinations, for example, are a part. As [[John Stuart Mill]] put it in the mid-19th century, matter is the "permanent possibility of sensation".<ref>Mill, J.S., "An Examination of Sir William Rowan Hamilton's Philosophy", in A.J. Ayer and Ramond Winch (eds.), British Empirical Philosophers, Simon and Schuster, New York, NY, 1968.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> Mill's empiricism went a significant step beyond Hume in still another respect: in maintaining that induction is necessary for ''all'' meaningful knowledge including mathematics. As summarized by D.W. Hamlin: {{quote|[Mill] claimed that mathematical truths were merely very highly confirmed generalizations from experience; mathematical inference, generally conceived as deductive [and ''a priori''] in nature, Mill set down as founded on induction. Thus, in Mill's philosophy there was no real place for knowledge based on relations of ideas. In his view logical and mathematical necessity is psychological; we are merely unable to conceive any other possibilities than those that logical and mathematical propositions assert. This is perhaps the most extreme version of empiricism known, but it has not found many defenders.<ref name = MEP2/>}} Mill's empiricism thus held that knowledge of any kind is not from direct experience but an inductive inference from direct experience.<ref>Wilson, Fred (2005), "John Stuart Mill", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.</ref> The problems other philosophers have had with Mill's position center around the following issues: Firstly, Mill's formulation encounters difficulty when it describes what direct experience is by differentiating only between actual and possible sensations. This misses some key discussion concerning conditions under which such "groups of permanent possibilities of sensation" might exist in the first place. Berkeley put God in that gap; the phenomenalists, including Mill, essentially left the question unanswered. In the end, lacking an acknowledgement of an aspect of "reality" that goes beyond mere "possibilities of sensation", such a position leads to a version of subjective idealism. Questions of how floor beams continue to support a floor while unobserved, how trees continue to grow while unobserved and untouched by human hands, etc., remain unanswered, and perhaps unanswerable in these terms.<ref name = MEP2/><ref name=MEP6>Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Phenomenalism", vol. 6, p. 131.</ref> Secondly, Mill's formulation leaves open the unsettling possibility that the "gap-filling entities are purely possibilities and not actualities at all".<ref name="MEP6"/> Thirdly, Mill's position, by calling mathematics merely another species of inductive inference, misapprehends mathematics. It fails to fully consider the structure and method of [[mathematical science]], the products of which are arrived at through an internally consistent [[deductive reasoning|deductive]] set of procedures which do not, either today or at the time Mill wrote, fall under the agreed meaning of [[inductive reasoning|induction]].<ref name=MEP2>Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Empiricism", vol. 2, p. 503.</ref><ref name="MEP6"/><ref>Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Axiomatic Method", vol. 5, pp. 188–89, 191ff.</ref> The phenomenalist phase of post-Humean empiricism ended by the 1940s, for by that time it had become obvious that statements about physical things could not be translated into statements about actual and possible sense data.<ref>Bolender, John (1998), "Factual Phenomenalism: A Supervenience Theory"', Sorites, no. 9, pp. 16–31.</ref> If a physical object statement is to be translatable into a sense-data statement, the former must be at least deducible from the latter. But it came to be realized that there is no finite set of statements about actual and possible sense-data from which we can deduce even a single physical-object statement. The translating or paraphrasing statement must be couched in terms of normal observers in normal conditions of observation. There is, however, no ''finite'' set of statements that are couched in purely sensory terms and can express the satisfaction of the condition of the presence of a normal observer. According to phenomenalism, to say that a normal observer is present is to make the hypothetical statement that were a doctor to inspect the observer, the observer would appear to the doctor to be normal. But, of course, the doctor himself must be a normal observer. If we are to specify this doctor's normality in sensory terms, we must make reference to a second doctor who, when inspecting the sense organs of the first doctor, would himself have to have the sense data a normal observer has when inspecting the sense organs of a subject who is a normal observer. And if we are to specify in sensory terms that the second doctor is a normal observer, we must refer to a third doctor, and so on (also see the [[Third Man Argument|third man]]).<ref>Berlin, Isaiah (2004), The Refutation of Phenomenalism, Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library.</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Chisholm |first1=Roderick M. |date=September 9, 1948 |title=The Problem of Empiricism |journal=The Journal of Philosophy |volume=45 |issue=19 |pages=512–17 |jstor=2019108 |doi=10.2307/2019108}}</ref> ===Logical empiricism=== {{Main|Logical positivism}} Logical empiricism (also ''logical positivism'' or ''neopositivism'') was an early 20th-century attempt to synthesize the essential ideas of British empiricism (e.g. a strong emphasis on sensory experience as the basis for knowledge) with certain insights from [[mathematical logic]] that had been developed by [[Gottlob Frege]] and [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]]. Some of the key figures in this movement were [[Otto Neurath]], [[Moritz Schlick]] and the rest of the [[Vienna Circle]], along with [[A. J. Ayer]], [[Rudolf Carnap]] and [[Hans Reichenbach]]. The neopositivists subscribed to a notion of philosophy as the conceptual clarification of the methods, insights and discoveries of the sciences. They saw in the logical symbolism elaborated by Frege (1848–1925) and [[Bertrand Russell]] (1872–1970) a powerful instrument that could rationally reconstruct all scientific discourse into an ideal, logically perfect, language that would be free of the ambiguities and deformations of natural language. This gave rise to what they saw as metaphysical pseudoproblems and other conceptual confusions. By combining Frege's thesis that all mathematical truths are logical with the early Wittgenstein's idea that all [[logical truth]]s are mere linguistic [[tautology (logic)|tautologies]], they arrived at a twofold classification of all propositions: the "analytic" (''a priori'') and the "synthetic" (''a posteriori'').<ref>[[Peter Achinstein|Achinstein, Peter]], and [[Stephen Francis Barker|Barker, Stephen F.]] (1969), The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> On this basis, they formulated a strong principle of demarcation between sentences that have sense and those that do not: the so-called "[[verification principle]]". Any sentence that is not purely logical, or is unverifiable, is devoid of meaning. As a result, most metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic and other traditional philosophical problems came to be considered pseudoproblems.<ref>Barone, Francesco (1986), Il neopositivismo logico, Laterza, Roma Bari.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> In the extreme empiricism of the neopositivists—at least before the 1930s—any genuinely synthetic assertion must be reducible to an ultimate assertion (or set of ultimate assertions) that expresses direct observations or perceptions. In later years, Carnap and Neurath abandoned this sort of ''phenomenalism'' in favor of a rational reconstruction of knowledge into the language of an objective spatio-temporal physics. That is, instead of translating sentences about physical objects into sense-data, such sentences were to be translated into so-called ''protocol sentences'', for example, "''X'' at location ''Y'' and at time ''T'' observes such and such".<ref>[[Nicholas Rescher|Rescher, Nicholas]] (1985), The Heritage of Logical Positivism, University Press of America, Lanham, MD.</ref> The central theses of logical positivism (verificationism, the analytic–synthetic distinction, reductionism, etc.) came under sharp attack after World War II by thinkers such as [[Nelson Goodman]], [[Willard Van Orman Quine|W. V. Quine]], [[Hilary Putnam]], [[Karl Popper]], and [[Richard Rorty]]. By the late 1960s, it had become evident to most{{who|date=April 2021}} philosophers that the movement had pretty much run its course, though its influence is still significant among contemporary [[analytic philosophy|analytic philosophers]] such as [[Michael Dummett]] and other [[anti-realism|anti-realists]]. ===Pragmatism=== In the late 19th and early 20th century, several forms of [[pragmatism|pragmatic philosophy]] arose. The ideas of pragmatism, in its various forms, developed mainly from discussions between [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[William James]] when both men were at Harvard in the 1870s. James popularized the term "pragmatism", giving Peirce full credit for its patrimony, but Peirce later demurred from the tangents that the movement was taking, and redubbed what he regarded as the original idea with the name of "pragmaticism". Along with its ''[[pragmatic theory of truth]]'', this perspective integrates the basic insights of empirical (experience-based) and [[rationalism|rational]] (concept-based) thinking. [[File:Charles Sanders Peirce theb3558.jpg|thumb|upright|[[Charles Sanders Peirce]]]] Charles Peirce (1839–1914) was highly influential in laying the groundwork for today's empirical [[scientific method]].<ref>{{Cite book |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/peirce/ |title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|last=Burch|first=Robert|date=2017|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2017}}</ref> Although Peirce severely criticized many elements of Descartes' peculiar brand of rationalism, he did not reject rationalism outright. Indeed, he concurred with the main ideas of rationalism, most importantly the idea that rational concepts can be meaningful and the idea that rational concepts necessarily go beyond the data given by empirical observation. In later years he even emphasized the concept-driven side of the then ongoing debate between strict empiricism and strict rationalism, in part to counterbalance the excesses to which some of his cohorts had taken pragmatism under the "data-driven" strict-empiricist view. Among Peirce's major contributions was to place [[inductive reasoning]] and [[deductive reasoning]] in a complementary rather than competitive mode, the latter of which had been the primary trend among the educated since David Hume wrote a century before. To this, Peirce added the concept of [[abductive reasoning]]. The combined three forms of reasoning serve as a primary conceptual foundation for the empirically based scientific method today. Peirce's approach "presupposes that (1) the objects of knowledge are real things, (2) the characters (properties) of real things do not depend on our perceptions of them, and (3) everyone who has sufficient experience of real things will agree on the truth about them. According to Peirce's doctrine of [[fallibilism]], the conclusions of science are always tentative. The rationality of the scientific method does not depend on the certainty of its conclusions, but on its self-corrective character: by continued application of the method science can detect and correct its own mistakes, and thus eventually lead to the discovery of truth".<ref>Ward, Teddy (n.d.), "Empiricism", [http://personal.ecu.edu/mccartyr/american/leap/empirici.htm Eprint] {{Webarchive|url=https://archive.today/20120714183655/http://personal.ecu.edu/mccartyr/american/leap/empirici.htm |date=2012-07-14 }}.</ref> [[File:Wm james.jpg|thumb|upright|right|[[William James]]]] In his Harvard "Lectures on Pragmatism" (1903), Peirce enumerated what he called the "three cotary propositions of pragmatism" ([[Latin|L:]] ''cos, cotis'' whetstone), saying that they "put the edge on the [[pragmatic maxim|maxim of pragmatism]]". First among these, he listed the peripatetic-thomist observation mentioned above, but he further observed that this link between sensory perception and intellectual conception is a two-way street. That is, it can be taken to say that whatever we find in the intellect is also incipiently in the senses. Hence, if theories are theory-laden then so are the senses, and perception itself can be seen as a species of [[abductive reasoning|abductive inference]], its difference being that it is beyond control and hence beyond critique—in a word, incorrigible. This in no way conflicts with the fallibility and revisability of scientific concepts, since it is only the immediate percept in its unique individuality or "thisness"—what the [[Scholastics]] called its ''[[haecceity]]''—that stands beyond control and correction. Scientific concepts, on the other hand, are general in nature, and transient sensations do in another sense find correction within them. This notion of perception as abduction has received periodic revivals in [[artificial intelligence]] and [[cognitive science]] research, most recently for instance with the work of [[Irvin Rock]] on ''[[indirect perception]]''.<ref>Rock, Irvin (1983), The Logic of Perception, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref><ref>Rock, Irvin, (1997) Indirect Perception, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> Around the beginning of the 20th century, William James (1842–1910) coined the term "[[radical empiricism]]" to describe an offshoot of his form of pragmatism, which he argued could be dealt with separately from his pragmatism—though in fact the two concepts are intertwined in James's published lectures. James maintained that the empirically observed "directly apprehended universe needs ... no extraneous trans-empirical connective support",<ref>James, William (1911), The Meaning of Truth.</ref> by which he meant to rule out the perception that there can be any [[value added]] by seeking [[supernatural]] explanations for [[nature|natural]] [[phenomena]]. James' "radical empiricism" is thus ''not'' radical in the context of the term "empiricism", but is instead fairly consistent with the modern use of the term "[[empirical]]". His method of argument in arriving at this view, however, still readily encounters debate within philosophy even today. [[John Dewey]] (1859–1952) modified James' pragmatism to form a theory known as [[instrumentalism]]. The role of sense experience in Dewey's theory is crucial, in that he saw experience as unified totality of things through which everything else is interrelated. Dewey's basic thought, in accordance with empiricism, was that [[reality]] is determined by past experience. Therefore, humans adapt their past experiences of things to perform experiments upon and test the pragmatic values of such experience. The value of such experience is measured experientially and scientifically, and the results of such tests generate ideas that serve as instruments for future experimentation,<ref>Dewey, John (1906), Studies in Logical Theory.{{page needed|date=December 2013}}</ref> in physical sciences as in ethics.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1353/jsp.2011.0000 |title=What Experimentalism Means in Ethics |year=2011 |last1=Weber |first1=Eric Thomas |journal=The Journal of Speculative Philosophy |volume=25 |pages=98–115|s2cid=144868257 }}</ref> Thus, ideas in Dewey's system retain their empiricist flavour in that they are only known ''a posteriori''. ==See also== {{div col}} * {{annotated link|Abstract empiricism}} * {{annotated link|Empirical idealism}} * {{annotated link|Empirical realism}} * {{annotated link|Empirical relationship}} * {{annotated link|Empirical research}} * {{annotated link|Empirical sociology}} * {{annotated link|Feminist empiricism}} * {{annotated link|Ground truth}} * {{annotated link|History of scientific method}} * {{annotated link|Inquiry}} * {{annotated link|Kantian empiricism}} * {{annotated link|Natural philosophy}} * {{annotated link|Naturalism (philosophy)|Naturalism}} * {{annotated link|Objectivity (philosophy)|Objectivity}} * {{annotated link|Positivism}} * {{annotated link|Psychological nativism}} * {{annotated link|Quasi-empirical method}} * {{annotated link|Sensualism}} * {{Annotated link|Transcendental Empiricism}}{{div col end}} ==Endnotes== {{Reflist}} ==References== {{Refbegin|30em}} * Achinstein, Peter, and Barker, Stephen F. (1969), ''The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science'', Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD. * [[Aristotle]], "[[On the Soul]]" (''De Anima''), [[W. S. Hett]] (trans.), pp. 1–203 in ''Aristotle, Volume 8'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[Heinemann (book publisher)|William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1936. * Aristotle, ''[[Posterior Analytics]]''. * Barone, Francesco (1986), ''Il neopositivismo logico'', Laterza, Roma Bari * Berlin, Isaiah (2004), ''The Refutation of Phenomenalism'', Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library. * Bolender, John (1998), "Factual Phenomenalism: A Supervenience Theory"', ''Sorites'', no. 9, pp. 16–31. * Chisolm, R. (1948), "The Problem of Empiricism", ''Journal of Philosophy'' 45, 512–17. * Dewey, John (1906), ''Studies in Logical Theory''. * ''Encyclopædia Britannica'', "Empiricism", vol. 4, p. 480. * [[David Hume|Hume, D.]], ''[[A Treatise of Human Nature]]'', L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), Oxford University Press, London, UK, 1975. * Hume, David. "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", in ''Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals'', 2nd edition, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1902. [http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4320/4320-h/4320-h.htm Gutenberg press full-text] * James, William (1911), ''The Meaning of Truth''. * [[Morris T. Keeton|Keeton, Morris T.]] (1962), "Empiricism", pp. 89–90 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ. * Leftow, Brian (ed., 2006), ''Aquinas: Summa Theologiae, Questions on God'', pp. vii ''et seq''. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Development of Aristotle's Thought", vol. 1, pp. 153ff. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "George Berkeley", vol. 1, p. 297. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Empiricism", vol. 2, p. 503. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Mathematics, Foundations of", vol. 5, pp. 188–89. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Axiomatic Method", vol. 5, pp. 192ff. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Epistemological Discussion", subsections on "A Priori Knowledge" and "Axioms". * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Phenomenalism", vol. 6, p. 131. * ''Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (1969), "Thomas Aquinas", subsection on "Theory of Knowledge", vol. 8, pp. 106–07. * Marconi, Diego (2004), "Fenomenismo"', in [[Gianni Vattimo]] and Gaetano Chiurazzi (eds.), ''L'Enciclopedia Garzanti di Filosofia'', 3rd edition, Garzanti, Milan, Italy. * Markie, P. (2004), "Rationalism vs. Empiricism" in Edward D. Zalta (ed.), ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism/ Eprint]. * [[Nicholas Maxwell|Maxwell, Nicholas]] (1998), ''The Comprehensibility of the Universe: A New Conception of Science'', Oxford University Press, Oxford. * Mill, J.S., "An Examination of Sir William Rowan Hamilton's Philosophy", in A.J. Ayer and Ramond Winch (eds.), ''British Empirical Philosophers'', Simon and Schuster, New York, NY, 1968. * Morick, H. (1980), ''Challenges to Empiricism'', [[Hackett Publishing]], Indianapolis, IN. * [[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, C.S.]], "Lectures on Pragmatism", Cambridge, Massachusetts, March 26 – May 17, 1903. Reprinted in part, ''Collected Papers'', CP 5.14–212. Published in full with editor's introduction and commentary, Patricia Ann Turisi (ed.), ''Pragmatism as a Principle and Method of Right Thinking: The 1903 Harvard "Lectures on Pragmatism"'', State University of New York Press, Albany, NY, 1997. Reprinted, pp. 133–241, Peirce Edition Project (eds.), ''The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 2 (1893–1913)'', [[Indiana University Press]], Bloomington, IN, 1998. * Rescher, Nicholas (1985), ''The Heritage of Logical Positivism'', University Press of America, Lanham, MD. * [[Irvin Rock|Rock, Irvin]] (1983), ''The Logic of Perception'', MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. * Rock, Irvin, (1997) ''Indirect Perception'', MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. * [[Dagobert D. Runes|Runes, D.D.]] (ed., 1962), ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ. * Sini, Carlo (2004), "Empirismo", in Gianni Vattimo et al. (eds.), ''Enciclopedia Garzanti della Filosofia''. * Solomon, Robert C., and Higgins, Kathleen M. (1996), ''A Short History of Philosophy'', pp. 68–74. <!--publisher--> * Sorabji, Richard (1972), ''Aristotle on Memory''. <!--publisher--> * Thornton, Stephen (1987), ''Berkeley's Theory of Reality'', [http://www.ul.ie/~philos/vol1/berkel.html Eprint] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110918113600/http://www.ul.ie/~philos/vol1/berkel.html |date=2011-09-18 }} * Vanzo, Alberto (2014), "From Empirics to Empiricists", ''Intellectual History Review'', 2014, Eprint available [http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/17496977.2014.914650 here] and [https://web.archive.org/web/20150427164746/http://www.albertovanzo.net/papers/From_Empirics_to_Empiricists-libre.pdf here]. * Ward, Teddy (n.d.), "Empiricism", [https://archive.today/20120714183655/http://personal.ecu.edu/mccartyr/american/leap/empirici.htm Eprint]. * Wilson, Fred (2005), "John Stuart Mill", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ Eprint]. {{Refend}} ==External links== {{wikiquote}} {{Commonscat|Empiricism}} *{{Cite IEP |url-id=british-empiricism|title=British Empiricism|author-last=Fasko|author-first=Manuel|author-last2=West|author-first2=Peter}} *{{cite SEP |url-id=rationalism-empiricism |title=Rationalism vs. Empiricism}} *{{InPho|taxonomy|2382|Rationalism vs. Empiricism}} *{{In Our Time|Empiricism|p004y28g|Empiricism}} *[http://chaospet.com/250 Empiricist Man] {{logic}} {{epistemology}} {{philosophy of science}} {{Philosophy topics}} {{analytic philosophy}} {{Positivism}} {{Science and technology studies}} {{Western culture}} {{Catholic philosophy footer}} {{Authority control}} [[Category:Empiricism| ]] [[Category:Justification (epistemology)]] [[Category:Philosophical methodology]] [[Category:Internalism and externalism]] [[Category:Philosophy of science]] [[Category:Empirical laws|*]] [[Category:Epistemological schools and traditions]] Summary: Please note that all contributions to Christianpedia may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here. You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see Christianpedia:Copyrights for details). Do not submit copyrighted work without permission! Cancel Editing help (opens in new window) Templates used on this page: Empiricism (edit) Template:About (edit) Template:Analytic philosophy (edit) Template:Annotated link (edit) Template:Authority control (edit) Template:Blockquote (edit) Template:Blockquote/styles.css (edit) Template:Catalog lookup link (edit) Template:Catholic philosophy footer (edit) Template:Circa (edit) Template:Citation needed (edit) Template:Cite IEP (edit) Template:Cite SEP (edit) Template:Cite book (edit) Template:Cite journal (edit) Template:Cite web (edit) Template:Commons category (edit) Template:Commonscat (edit) Template:Div col (edit) Template:Div col/styles.css (edit) Template:Div col end (edit) Template:Epistemology (edit) Template:Epistemology sidebar (edit) Template:Fix (edit) Template:ISBN (edit) Template:InPho (edit) Template:In Our Time (edit) Template:Logic (edit) Template:Main (edit) Template:Main other (edit) Template:Multiple image (edit) Template:Multiple image/styles.css (edit) Template:Page needed (edit) Template:Philosophy of science (edit) Template:Philosophy topics (edit) Template:Positivism (edit) Template:Quote (edit) Template:Refbegin (edit) Template:Refbegin/styles.css (edit) Template:Refend (edit) Template:Reflist (edit) Template:Reflist/styles.css (edit) Template:Research (edit) Template:Science and technology studies (edit) Template:Short description (edit) Template:Sister project (edit) Template:Trim (edit) Template:Use British English (edit) Template:Webarchive (edit) Template:Western culture (edit) Template:Who (edit) Template:Wikiquote (edit) Template:Yesno-no (edit) Template:Yesno-yes (edit) Module:Arguments (edit) Module:Catalog lookup link (edit) Module:Check for unknown parameters (edit) Module:Check isxn (edit) Module:Citation/CS1 (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/COinS (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/Configuration (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/Date validation (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/Identifiers (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/Utilities (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/Whitelist (edit) Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css (edit) Module:Format link (edit) Module:Hatnote (edit) Module:Hatnote/styles.css (edit) Module:Hatnote list (edit) Module:Labelled list hatnote (edit) Module:Multiple image (edit) Module:Unsubst (edit) Module:Yesno (edit) Discuss this page