Science Warning: You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you log in or create an account, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.Anti-spam check. Do not fill this in! === Scientific method === [[File:The Scientific Method.svg|thumb|A diagram variant of scientific method represented as an [[Scientific method#Elements of the scientific method|ongoing process]]|alt=6 steps of the scientific method in a loop]] Scientific research involves using the [[scientific method]], which seeks to [[objectivity (science)|objectively]] explain the events of [[nature]] in a [[reproducible]] way.<ref name= difrancia1976>{{cite book | last= di Francia | first= Giuliano Toraldo | chapter = The method of physics | title = The Investigation of the Physical World| location = Cambridge, United Kingdom | publisher = Cambridge University Press| year=1976 | pages = 1–52 | isbn=978-0-521-29925-1|quote=The amazing point is that for the first time since the discovery of mathematics, a method has been introduced, the results of which have an intersubjective value!}}</ref> Scientists usually take for granted a set of basic assumptions that are needed to justify the scientific method: there is an [[objective reality]] shared by all rational observers; this objective reality is governed by [[natural law]]s; these laws were discovered by means of systematic [[observation]] and experimentation.<ref name="Heilbron"/> Mathematics is essential in the formation of [[hypothesis|hypotheses]], [[Theory|theories]], and laws, because it is used extensively in quantitative modeling, observing, and collecting [[measurements]].<ref name="popper2002e">{{cite book |last=Popper |first=Karl R. |url=https://archive.org/details/logicscientificd00popp_574 |title=The Logic of Scientific Discovery |publisher=Routledge Classics |year=2002e |isbn=978-0-415-27844-7 |location=New York |pages=[https://archive.org/details/logicscientificd00popp_574/page/n133 3]–26 |chapter=The problem of the empirical basis |oclc=59377149 |orig-date=1959 |url-access=limited}}</ref> Statistics is used to summarize and analyze data, which allows scientists to assess the reliability of experimental results.<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Diggle |first1=Peter J. |author-link=Peter Diggle |title=Statistics and Scientific Method: An Introduction for Students and Researchers |last2=Chetwynd |first2=Amanda G. |author2-link=Amanda Chetwynd |year= 2011 |publisher=[[Oxford University Press]] |isbn=978-0199543182 |pages=1, 2}}</ref> In the scientific method, an explanatory [[thought experiment]] or hypothesis is put forward as an explanation using [[Occam's razor|parsimony principles]] and is expected to seek [[consilience]] – fitting with other accepted facts related to an observation or scientific question.<ref name= EOWilson>{{cite book| last = Wilson | first = Edward | title = Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge | publisher = Vintage | location = New York | year = 1999 | isbn = 978-0-679-76867-8}}</ref> This tentative explanation is used to make [[falsifiable]] predictions, which are typically posted before being tested by experimentation. Disproof of a prediction is evidence of progress.<ref name = difrancia1976 />{{Rp|pages=4–5}}<ref name = fara2009>{{cite book | last= Fara | first= Patricia | author-link= Patricia Fara | year= 2009 | chapter= Decisions | title= Science: A Four Thousand Year History | location= Oxford, United Kingdom | publisher= Oxford University Press | isbn= 978-0-19-922689-4 | page= [https://archive.org/details/sciencefourthous00fara/page/408 408] | chapter-url= https://archive.org/details/sciencefourthous00fara/page/306}}</ref> Experimentation is especially important in science to help establish [[causality|causal relationships]] to avoid the [[correlation does not imply causation|correlation fallacy]], though in some sciences such as astronomy or geology, a predicted observation might be more appropriate.<ref name="Aldrich1995">{{Cite journal|last=Aldrich |first=John |journal=Statistical Science |volume=10 |year=1995 |pages=364–376 |title=Correlations Genuine and Spurious in Pearson and Yule |jstor=2246135 |doi=10.1214/ss/1177009870 |issue=4 |doi-access=free }}</ref> When a hypothesis proves unsatisfactory, it is modified or discarded.<ref name = Nola2005k>{{cite book| last1= Nola | first1= Robert | last2= Irzik | first2= Gürol | year= 2005k | chapter = naive inductivism as a methodology in science | title= Philosophy, science, education and culture | volume= 28 | series=Science & technology education library | isbn= 978-1-4020-3769-6 | publisher= Springer | pages = 207–230 }}</ref> If the hypothesis survived testing, it may become adopted into the framework of a [[scientific theory]], a [[deductive logic|valid]]ly [[reason]]ed, self-consistent model or framework for describing the behavior of certain natural events. A theory typically describes the behavior of much broader sets of observations than a hypothesis; commonly, a large number of hypotheses can be logically bound together by a single theory. Thus a theory is a hypothesis explaining various other hypotheses. In that vein, theories are formulated according to most of the same scientific principles as hypotheses. Scientists may generate a [[Scientific modelling|model]], an attempt to describe or depict an observation in terms of a logical, physical or mathematical representation and to generate new hypotheses that can be tested by experimentation.<ref name = Nola2005j>{{cite book| last1= Nola | first1= Robert | last2= Irzik | first2= Gürol | year=2005j | chapter = The aims of science and critical inquiry | title= Philosophy, science, education and culture | volume= 28 | series= Science & technology education library | isbn= 978-1-4020-3769-6 | publisher= Springer | pages = 207–230 }}</ref> While performing experiments to test hypotheses, scientists may have a preference for one outcome over another.<ref>{{cite web| last= van Gelder | first= Tim | year= 1999 | url= http://www.philosophy.unimelb.edu.au/tgelder/papers/HeadsIWin.pdf | title="Heads I win, tails you lose": A Foray Into the Psychology of Philosophy | publisher= University of Melbourne | access-date= March 28, 2008 |archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20080409054240/http://www.philosophy.unimelb.edu.au/tgelder/papers/HeadsIWin.pdf <!-- Bot retrieved archive --> |archive-date = April 9, 2008}}</ref><ref>{{cite web | last= Pease | first= Craig | date= September 6, 2006 | archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20100619154617/http://law-and-science.net/Science4BLJ/Scientific_Method/Deliberate.bias/Text.htm | archive-date = June 19, 2010 | title= Chapter 23. Deliberate bias: Conflict creates bad science | website= Science for Business, Law and Journalism | publisher=Vermont Law School| url= http://law-and-science.net/Science4BLJ/Scientific_Method/Deliberate.bias/Text.htm}}</ref> Eliminating the bias can be achieved by transparency, careful [[Design of experiments|experimental design]], and a thorough [[peer review]] process of the experimental results and conclusions.<ref>{{cite book | first= David | last= Shatz | year = 2004 | title= Peer Review: A Critical Inquiry | publisher= Rowman & Littlefield | isbn= 978-0-7425-1434-8 | oclc= 54989960}}</ref><ref>{{cite book | first= Sheldon | last= Krimsky | year= 2003 | title= Science in the Private Interest: Has the Lure of Profits Corrupted the Virtue of Biomedical Research | publisher= Rowman & Littlefield | isbn= 978-0-7425-1479-9 | oclc= 185926306 | url= https://archive.org/details/scienceinprivate0000krim }}</ref> After the results of an experiment are announced or published, it is normal practice for independent researchers to double-check how the research was performed, and to follow up by performing similar experiments to determine how dependable the results might be.<ref>{{cite book | first= Ruth Ellen | last= Bulger | year= 2002 |author2= Heitman, Elizabeth |author3= Reiser, Stanley Joel | title= The Ethical Dimensions of the Biological and Health Sciences | edition= 2nd | isbn= 978-0-521-00886-0 | publisher= Cambridge University Press | oclc= 47791316 }}</ref> Taken in its entirety, the scientific method allows for highly creative problem solving while minimizing the effects of subjective and [[confirmation bias]].<ref name= backer>{{cite web|last= Backer |first= Patricia Ryaby |date= October 29, 2004 |url= http://www.engr.sjsu.edu/pabacker/scientific_method.htm |title= What is the scientific method? |publisher= San Jose State University |access-date=March 28, 2008 |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20080408082917/http://www.engr.sjsu.edu/pabacker/scientific_method.htm |archive-date= April 8, 2008 }}</ref> [[Intersubjective verifiability]], the ability to reach a consensus and reproduce results, is fundamental to the creation of all scientific knowledge.<ref name="ziman1978c">{{cite book |last=Ziman |first=John |title=Reliable knowledge: An exploration of the grounds for belief in science |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1978c |isbn=978-0-521-22087-3 |location=Cambridge |pages=[https://archive.org/details/reliableknowledg00john/page/42 42–76] |chapter=Common observation |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/reliableknowledg00john/page/42}}</ref> Summary: Please note that all contributions to Christianpedia may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here. You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see Christianpedia:Copyrights for details). Do not submit copyrighted work without permission! Cancel Editing help (opens in new window) Discuss this page